We who are exponents of mathematics have a responsibility to cast a jaundiced eye at the misappropriation of mathematical tools. I think, however, we are too often flattered by the "math envy" exhibited by those who write fanciful equations to make their work look more algebraic and less prosaic. Let us be on guard.
My thoughts were turned in this direction by some coincidences: The death of Serge Lang, the appearance of William Dembski on The Daily Show, and a recollection of a passage from Claude Lévi-Strauss.
Lang vs. Huntington
Lang was a tireless combatant against anything he perceived as inaccurate or sloppily reasoned. When political scientist Samuel Huntington was nominated for membership in the National Academy of Sciences (of which Lang was already a member), Lang launched a vigorous and successful campaign to defeat Huntington's candidacy for the honor. What mathematical sin had Huntington committed? Lang was adamant that anyone who appropriated mathematical language was obligated to respect its consequences. Huntington's use of quasi-algebraic reasoning in a 1971 paper (see Sullivan, 1998) resulted in such statements as
political instability = (political participation)/(political institutionalization).
What are we to make of this? Apparently Huntington posits that political instability will grow as political participation increases. Inversely, instability will decrease as political institutionalization increases. It is difficult to know what to make of this, given that Huntington did not bother to define his terms specifically enough to allow anyone to check out his equations. (Nor, for that matter, did he define in what units the quantities were to be given.)
While this simple example does not on its own refute Huntington's argument (which I lack the background to address anyway), it nevertheless shows a mathematical formalism being pressed into duty where it adds nothing to (and, indeed, is likely to detract from) any accompanying narrative discussion.
Claude Lévi-Strauss
Lévi-Strauss is the grand old man of structuralism, a school of thought no longer popular in an era of deconstruction. Still, his name is well-known in anthropology and it would be unkind to dismiss him because of his current unfashionability. However, when I saw the news of Serge Lang's death and browsed several articles about Lang's career, I recalled having seen something similar to Huntington's expropriation of mathematics, but in a more literary context. I couldn't remember who had written it. Thanks to a friend with a better recollection than mine, I soon had from him the exact quote and the name of the author of same. Brace yourselves. Here is the quote, right out of Lévi-Strauss's The Structural Study of Myth:
Finally, when we have succeeded in organizing a whole series of variants into a kind of permutation group, we are in a position to formulate the law of that group. Although it is not possible at the present stage to come closer than an approximate formulation which will certainly need to be refined in the future, it seems that every myth (considered as the aggregate of all its variants) corresponds to a formula of the following type:For whom do you think Lévi-Strauss wrote this? Professional mathematicians, who are unlikely to be reading about the structure of myth? Fellow anthropologists, who would not know the difference between a group and a tribe? While I am hesitant to make pronouncements out of hand about anthropology, a discipline in which I have had but one elementary college course, I do know just a little bit more about mathematics. For example, Lévi-Strauss says he can organize a series of myth variants into a "kind of permutation group". Okay, I know what a permutation group is. But then he purports to "formulate the law of that group". Law? Does he mean to characterize the group operation? If it's a permutation group, then the operation involves rearrangement of the components of its elements. I do see some items, variously called terms and functions, being rearranged, but what the heck is F? And how did a and a − 1 become inverses of each other? (As elements from [0, 1], where 1/2 is its own opposite?)
Here, with two terms, a and b, being given as well as two functions, x and y, of these terms, it is assumed that a relation of equivalence exists between two situations defined respectively by an inversion of terms and relations, under two conditions: (1) that one term be replaced by its opposite (in the above formula, a and a − 1); (2) that an inversion be made between the function value and the term value of two elements (above, y and a).
You know what? I think this is gibberish. The mathematical "formula" will be impenetrable to those who know no math and highly suspect to those who do. Perhaps I need to read the entire book. Perhaps I am simply not sophisticated enough to grasp the keen group-theoretical insight represented by Lévi-Strauss's formulation, but until someone enlightens me, I will tend to believe that the meaningfulness was in the author's head alone. Sorry, Claude.
William Dembski
Dr. Dembski is the current Wunderkind of Intelligent Design and is, surprisingly enough, an actual mathematician with an earned doctorate. Good for him! Dembski represents the other side of the "math envy" coin. Instead of applying mathematics where its applicability is doubtful, Dembski wields math as a bludgeon to hide the doubtfulness of his conclusions. My examples from Huntington and Lévi-Strauss showed mathematics going astray into foreign fields. Dembski, however, uses mathematics in logical chains of symbolic reasoning. What could be more suitable?
Mark Perakh provides the definitive take-down of Dembski's mathematism, the deliberate use of mathematics to obscure the paucity of one's arguments. In his on-line paper, A Consistent Inconsistency, Perakh homes in on an example in which Dembski just about gives the show away. Examine the following logical statements in ordinary prose:
Premise 1: E has occurred.Supposing that a satisfactory definition of "specified" was previously provided, the chain of reasoning is reasonably clear, is it not? However, Dembski is not content to explain with words what he can tart up in mathematical language to impress the bourgeoisie:
Premise 2: E is specified.
Premise 3: If E is due to chance, then E has small probability.
Premise 4: Specified events of small probability do not occur by chance.
Premise 5: E is not due to regularity.
Premise 6: E is due either to a regularity, chance or design.
Conclusion: E is due to design.
Premise 1: oc(E)See how much better this is? While the general reader might peruse Dembski's prose argument and follow the steps with a modicum of confidence, who but a logician would be more comfortable with the abbreviated and symbol-laden alternative? Dembski makes the mistake here (taken from his book The Design Inference and quoted in Perakh's review) of revealing how unnecessary is his resort to mathematical formalism. While mathematics can shed light on complex problems, it can also be used to confuse and confound. With his many articles and books, Dembski has raised "mathematism" to a fine art, so that all who do not understand his symbols but agree with his objectives (replacing evolution with creationism) can praise his intellectual attainments and the supposed rigor of his arguments.
Premise 2: sp(E)
Premise 3: ch(E) → SP(E)
Premise 4: ∀X[oc(X) & sp(X) & SP(X) → ch(X)]
Premise 5: ∼reg(E)
Premise 6: reg(E) ∨ ch(E) ∨ des(E)
Conclusion: des(E)
In Summation
Mathematics is powerful, so people seek to enlist its support for their positions. This is completely understandable. But mathematics is also demanding. If you cannot meet its demands for consistency and rigor, then back away slowly from it. You'll be safer that way. If, on the other hand, you are mathematically competent, then the question becomes whether you use math to inform (as with fruitful mathematical models in physics) or distract (à la Dembski and his creationist tracts). Let's be honest about math.
6 comments:
Martin Luther’s “Disputatio pro Declaratione Virtutis Indulgentiarum,” Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, and Kurt Gödel’s “On Formally Undecidable Propositions” stand among the most important texts ever written. And we must count Zeno’s “Who Owns Mathematics?” as one of them.
Yet I think simply regarding Zeno’s work as one of many important texts does it an injustice. Many have already lavished praise on this week-old posting. Fredrick von Claptrap writes that “After reading ‘Who Owns Mathematics?” “the scales fell from my eyes.” So profound was Claptrap’s epiphany that he turned from a study of philosophers he now considers “frivolous,” among them Hegel, Heidegger, and Nietzsche, to devote himself to the fulltime study of Zeno. But Claptrap’s commendation pales in comparison to a noted Scientologist who began a study of axiomatic theology just three days after reading Zeno’s blog. The one-time Scientologist not only praises Zeno’s work but proves its greatness. He writes:
Assume Text N exists.
Premise: Some texts are part of the canon.
Premise: Some texts are not part of the canon.
Premise: Text N is not one of the texts that should not be part of the canon.
Therefore: Text N should be part of the cannon.
I could cite many more still more lavish tributes. But since no tribute can do Zeno’s work justice, let me close by citing an almost laconic review. “It [Who Owns Mathematics?”] is so clear that even an English major might understand it.” Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle each had their time; now is Zeno’s time.
Oh, geez.
Huntington's name came up at the Peace March in Washington this past weekend (i.e. Sept. 24, 2005). One of the speakers claimed that in the world situation we faced not a "clash of civilizations", but rather the old-fashioned, boring, but resilient "imperialism", albeit of a modern corporate variety.
This made a certain amount of sense to me.
By the way, have you prepared for the coming influenza pandemic? It may not be so bad, or it could be medium bad, or worse than that. And it may be years away - or maybe not.
There's a lot of math envy--especially in those pesky social sciences where it's impossible to isolate everything:). I know that Psychology is as guilty as anything else you have up there (Strauss was a Sociologist, as I recall). Of course we have math envy! You can be exact! When studying people, however, the ability to be exact often goes out the window.
(BTW, they didn't always use statistics--if you want to chuckle, read American Psychologist from the late 1800's to find out more.)
At this point, we basically try to use statistics, with the full knowledge that if we find anything "significant" there's still a very big possibility our results were just a fluke. Therefore, we also try to rely on repetition of studies--they aren't taken very seriously in our field unless the results have been replicated a few times, making the chance of "fluke results" far less likely (yet still possible!).
If anyone can figure out a way to "prove" ANYTHING in my field and could teach me such a methodology, I'd be eternally grateful. In the meantime we just have to "make do".
Sigh--what does one do when they want to study complicated matters such as people, anyway?
I would like to know the hypothesized previous definition of "specified." Near as I can tell, it must be something along the lines of, "something that, were it to happen, would challenge my view of things." Hence, specified events can't happen unless I get to concoct whatever lame-ass explanation I want for them.
Premise 1: E has occurred.
Premise 2: E is specified.
Premise 3: If E is due to chance, then E has small probability.
Premise 4: Specified events of small probability do not occur by chance.
Well, I guess that proves that every lotto game with a winner has been fixed. Call the police!
Post a Comment